Is There A Right To Health Care?
Bill Clinton ran for president last year by attacking the 1980s as a "decade of greed" —attacking the leveraged buyouts and hostile takeovers engineered by Wall Street financiers. I happen to think this trend in the 1980s was a good thing, a productive realignment in American business. But be that as it may, the irony is that President Clinton is now proposing a hostile takeover of his own, a hostile takeover on a scale far beyond anything that Wall Street capitalists ever dreamed of, a hostile takeover of one seventh of the nation's economy. I'm referring, of course, to his recently announced plan for health care "reform."
The Clinton plan in its present form involves a massive exercise
of coercion against physicians, employers, and patients alike. Most
people will be forced to do business through health insurance purchasing
cooperatives: government-backed monopolies that collect payments from
consumers and set the terms on which producers can offer their services.
Everyone will be forced to buy health care through these monopolies,
with employers forced to pay the lion's share of the bill. Physicians,
hospitals, and HMOs will be prohibited from dealing with patients
directly; they will be forced to offer their services through the
purchasing cooperatives, subject to highly restrictive rules.
Every right imposes some obligation on others.
What has brought us to this state of affairs? Socialism has
collapsed in the Soviet Union. The nations of Western Europe are trying
to trim back their welfare states, desperately looking for ways to
privatize. Yet in this country we are on the brink of a massive increase
in government subsidies and government controls. Why?
The full story is a long and complicated one, but the essential
cause, I think, is simple. The essential cause is the assumption that if
people have medical needs which are not being met, it is society's
responsibility to meet them. In the current debate over health care
reform, universal access has become the unquestioned goal, to which all
other considerations may be sacrificed. The assumption is that the needs
of recipients take precedence over the rights of physicians, hospitals,
insurers and drug companies—the producers of health care, the people
who deliver the goods—along with the rights of the taxpayers who are
going to have to pay for it. In other words, those with the ability to
provide health care are obliged to serve, while those with a need for
health care are entitled to make demands.
Indeed, it is often said that the need for health care constitutes a
right. President Clinton campaigned with the slogan, "Health care
should be a right, not a privilege." Opinion polls regularly show that
the belief in such a right is widespread, even within the medical
profession. The AMA's "Patient's Bill of Rights" includes the statement
that patients have a "right to essential health care."
If health care is a right, then government is responsible for
seeing that everyone has access to it, just as the right to property
means that government must protect us against theft. For the past thirty
years, the idea that people have a right to health care has led to
greater and greater government control over the medical profession and
the health care industry. The needs of the indigent, the needs of the
uninsured, the needs of the elderly, among other groups, have been put
forward as claims on public resources. Government has responded by
subsidizing these groups, and regulating physicians, insurers, and
pharmaceutical companies on their behalf. Now the Clinton Administration
proposes to make this right universal, to create a universal
entitlement, and to vastly expand government control.
In this context, I can state my own point in a sentence: there is
no such right. I will show you why the attempt to implement this alleged
right leads in practice to the suspension of the genuine rights of
doctors, patients, and the public at large. And I will show why the
concept of such a right is corrupt in theory. I want to stress at the
outset the importance of this issue. The long-term direction of public
policy is not set by electoral politics, or by horse-trading in
Congress, or by this or that court case. In the long term, at a basic
level, public policy is set by ideas—ideas about things are just and
worthy, what rights and obligations we have as individuals. The idea
that people have a right to health care is inimical to our genuine
liberties. The policies that flow from that idea are harmful to the
interests of doctors and patients alike. To fight against those
policies, we have to attack their root.
Liberty vs. Welfare Rights
Let's begin by defining our terms. A right is a principle that
specifies something which an individual should be free to have or do. A
right is an entitlement, something you possess free and clear, something
you can exercise without asking anyone else's permission. Because it is
an entitlement, not a privilege or favor, we do not owe anyone else any
gratitude for their recognition of our rights.
When we speak of rights, we invoke a concept that is fundamental to
our political system. Our country was founded on the principle that
individuals possess the "inalienable rights to life, liberty, and the
pursuit of happiness." Along with the right to property, which the
Founding Fathers also regarded as fundamental, these rights are known as
liberty rights, because they protect the right to act freely. The
wording of the Declaration of Independence is quite precise in this
regard. It attributes to us the right to the pursuit of happiness, not
to happiness per se. Society can't guarantee us happiness; that's our
own responsibility. All it can guarantee is the freedom to pursue it. In
the same way, the right to life is the right to act freely for one's
self-preservation. It is not a right to be immune from death by natural
causes, even an untimely death. And the right to property is the right
to act freely in the effort to acquire wealth, the right to buy and sell
and keep the fruits of one's labor. It is not a right to expect to be
given wealth.
The purpose of liberty rights is to protect individual autonomy.
They leave individuals responsible for their own lives, for meeting
their own needs. But they provide us with the social conditions we need
to carry out that responsibility: the freedom to act on the basis of our
own judgment, in pursuit of our own ends; and the right to use and
dispose of the material resources we have acquired by our efforts. These
rights reflect the assumption that individuals are ends in themselves,
who may not be used against their will for social purposes.
A doctor who waives his bill because I am indigent is offering a free gift; he retains his autonomy.
Let us consider what liberty rights mean in regard to medical care.
If we implemented them fully, patients would be free to choose the type
of care they want, and the particular health care providers they want
to see, in accordance with their needs and resources. They would be free
to choose whether they want health insurance, and if so, in what
amounts. Doctors and other providers would be free to offer their
services on whatever terms they choose. Prices would be governed not by
government fiat, but by competition in a market. Since this is an
imaginary state of affairs, no one can predict what mix of private
practitioners, HMOs, and other sorts of health plans would emerge. But
market forces would tend to ensure that patients have more choices than
they do now, that they would act more responsibly than many do at
present, and that they would pay actuarially fair prices for health
insurance—prices that reflect the actual risks associated with their
age, physical condition, and lifestyle. No one would be able to shift
his costs onto someone else. In a truly free market, I might add, there
would be no tax preference for obtaining health insurance through
employers, so most people would probably buy health insurance the way
they buy life insurance, auto insurance, or homeowners
insurance—directly from insurance companies. They would not have to fear
that losing their job, or changing the job, would mean losing their
coverage.
So that is what liberty rights—the classical rights to life,
liberty, and property—would mean in practice. The so-called "right" to
medical care is quite different. It is not merely the right to act—i.e.,
to seek medical care, and engage in exchanges with providers, free from
third party interference. It is a right to a good: actual care,
regardless of whether one can pay for it. The alleged right to medical
care is one instance of a broader category known as welfare rights.
Welfare rights in general are rights to goods: for example, a right to
food, shelter, education, a job, etc. This is one basic way in which
they are quite different from liberty rights, which are rights to
freedom of action, but don't guarantee that one will succeed in
obtaining any particular good one may be seeking.
Another difference has to do with the obligations imposed on other
people. Every right imposes some obligation on others. Liberty rights
impose negative obligations: the obligation not to interfere with one's
liberty. Such rights are secured by laws that prohibit murder, theft,
rape, fraud, and other crimes. But welfare rights impose on others the
positive obligation to provide the goods in question.
Health care does not grow on trees or fall from the sky. The
assertion of a right to medical care does not guarantee that there is
going to be any health care to distribute. The partisans of these rights
demand, with air of moral righteousness, that everyone have access to
this good. But a demand does not create anything. Health care has to be
produced by someone, and paid for by someone. One of the major arguments
offered by supporters of a right to health care is that health care is
an essential need. What good are our other liberties, they ask, if we
cannot get medical treatment for illness? But we must ask, in return:
why does need give someone a right? Fifty years ago, people whose
kidneys were failing needed dialysis every bit as much as they do today,
but there were no dialysis machines. Did they have a right to
protection against kidney failure? Was Mother Nature violating their
rights by making their kidneys fail without a remedy? It makes no sense
to say that need itself confers a right unless someone else has the
ability to meet that need. So any "right" to medical care imposes on
someone the obligation to provide care to those who cannot provide it
for themselves.
If I have such a right, some other person or group has the
involuntary, unchosen obligation to provide it. I stress the word
"involuntary." A right is an entitlement. If I have a right to medical
care, then I am entitled to the time, the effort, the ability, the
wealth, of whoever is going to be forced to provide that care. In other
words, I own a piece of the taxpayers who subsidize me. I own a piece of
the doctors who tend to me. The notion of a right to medical care goes
far beyond any notion of charity. A doctor who waives his bill because I
am indigent is offering a free gift; he retains his autonomy, and I owe
him gratitude. But if I have a right to care, then he is merely giving
me my due, and I owe him nothing. If others are forced to serve me in
the name of my right to care, then they are being used regardless of
their will as a means to my welfare. I am stressing this point because
many people do not appreciate that the very concept of welfare rights,
including the right to health care, is incompatible with the view of
individuals as ends in themselves.
I might add that the difference between charity and rights is very
well understood by the advocates of a right to health care. One of their
main arguments for using the language of rights is that it removes the
stigma associated with charity. A right is something for which you don't
owe anyone any gratitude. But notice the contradiction. The reason for
proposing such a right in the first place is the claim that certain
people cannot provide for themselves, and are thus dependent on other
people for their medical care. The advocates of a right to health care
then turn around and insist on using the concept of rights to disguise
the fact of dependence, to allow the recipients of government subsidies
to pretend that they are getting something they earned.
It is also worth noting that the Supreme Court has never recognized
a constitutional basis for any welfare right, including the right to
medical care. The Court recognizes that the concept of rights embodied
in our legal system is the concept of liberty rights. Welfare rights are
a product of later movements to expand the role of government beyond
the original conception of its role. In our constitutional system, there
is no requirement that the federal government provide health care.
Health care entitlements, unlike fundamental rights like freedom of
speech, have to be invented by legislators.
Effects of a Right to Health Care
Unfortunately, our legislators have been equal to the challenge.
They have invented such entitlements in spades. And that leads me to my
next point. When government attempts to implement a right to health
care, the result will be the abrogation of liberty rights. As with
money, bad rights drive out good ones. Let's review the major
consequences of implementing a right to medical care. I am going to use
illustrations from our current situation, but these consequences follow
inevitably from any approach: single payer, managed competition,
whatever.
When government attempts to implement a right to health care, the result will be the abrogation of liberty rights.
1) To begin with, of course, the government has
to tax some people to pay for medical subsidies offered to those it
considers to be in need. So the first consequence of implementing a
"right" to medical care is forced transfers of wealth from taxpayers to
the clientele of programs like Medicare and Medicaid. And this will
inflate the demand for health care services. Offering free or heavily
subsidized care is inevitably going to increase overall use of the
health care system.
Figures from the early years of the Medicaid program indicate the
vast increase in demand that can result. According to a Brookings
Institution study, in 1964, before Medicaid went into effect, those
above the poverty line saw physicians about 20 percent more frequently
than did the poor; by 1975, the poor were visiting physicians 18 percent
more often than the nonpoor. Again, before Medicaid, those with low
incomes had only half as many surgical procedures as those with
middle-class incomes; by 1970, the rate for low-income people was 40%
higher than for those with middle class incomes.[1] When Medicare was
instituted in 1966, the House Ways and Means Committee estimated that by
1990, allowing for inflation, the program would cost $12 billion; the
actual figure was $107 billion.[2] (Government forecasts of the costs of
entitlement programs are never accurate. In many cases, like this one,
they do not even get the order of magnitude correct.)
2) The cost explosion leads to the second major
consequence of implementing a "right" to medical care: restrictions on
the freedom of health care providers. During the debate over health care
policy in the 1960s, proponents of Medicare and Medicaid assured
doctors that they only wanted to pay for indigent care, and had no
intention of regulating the profession. Abraham Ribicoff, then Secretary
of Health, Education, and Welfare, said: "It should be absolutely no
concern to a physician where a patient gets the money."[3]
But of course the surge in demand for medical care led to rapid
price increases, along with abuses of the system by clients of the
government programs as well as by unscrupulous doctors and hospitals.
These problems had to be addressed somehow, and the result was a growing
web of controls: Professional Standards Review Organizations,
diagnosis-related groups, restrictions on balance billing, utilization
reviews. Under the managed care systems that have proliferated in the
effort to control costs, physicians have less and less autonomy to act
on their own best judgment about what is best for the patient. Dr.
Maurice Sislen has written: "A huge, complex, policing system has taken
the place of what used to be the doctor's responsibility to his patient.
Probably only a practicing physician can fully appreciate the magnitude
of the economic waste and moral degradation involved."[4]
3) A third major consequence of implementing a
right to health care is the increased burden imposed on consumers of
health care—the ones who were originally not in need of government
subsidies. As taxpayers, of course, they have to pay for all the
programs; that's point 1. But as consumers, they are also affected by
all the distortions of the market which these programs create. Everyone
pays the higher prices caused by the inflation of demand for medical
services, together with the increased costs of regulation and paperwork.
As people are priced out of the system, they are forced into managed
care systems that limit their choices of doctors.
Health insurance stipulations by states raise the cost of
insurance, and discourage employers from hiring certain kinds of
workers. For example, "community rating" laws require insurance
companies to offer policies for the same price to all people, regardless
of age, lifestyle, or physical condition. Since the actual risks depend
on these factors, what community rating means is that the young pay
higher prices to subsidize the elderly, the well subsidize the sick, and
those with healthy lifestyles subsidize those with unhealthy ones. As
an indication of the kind of subsidy involved, community rating in New
York nearly tripled the cost of insurance for a 30-year-old male.[5]
4) Yet another consequence is a growing demand for
equality in health care. If something is a human right, after all, then
it should be protected equally for all persons. Our system is based on
the idea of equality before the law. Now if we plug into this system the
additional idea that we all have a legal right to some good like health
care, the natural inference is that we all ought to receive that good
on a more or less equal footing. For example, in a 1989 survey for the
Harvard Community Health Plan, 90% of the respondents said that everyone
should have "a right to the best possible health care—as good as a
millionaire." Here's another example, a statement by Horace Deets, the
Executive Director of the American Association of Retired Persons:
"Ultimately, we must recognize that health care is not a commodity.
Those with more resources should not be able to purchase services while
those with less do without. Health care is a social good that should be
available to every person without regard to his resources."[6] And the
Clinton plan is clearly egalitarian. One of the explicit goals of the
proposal is to eliminate any "two-tier" system in which some people are
able to buy more or better health care than others.
5) The fifth consequence--the last one I'll
mention--is the collectivization of health care, and of health itself.
Just as a mixed economy treats wealth as a collective asset, which the
government is free to dispose of as it sees fit for "the common good,"
so a collectivized health care system treats the health of its members
as a collective asset. Under this regime, physicians no longer work for
their patients, with the overriding responsibility to act in their
interests. Instead, physicians are agents of "society" who must decide
the amount and the kind of care they give an individual patient by
reference to social needs, such as the need to control costs in the
system as a whole. Indeed, even the individual in such a system is urged
to protect his own health not because it is in his self-interest, but
because he has a responsibility to society not to impose too many costs
on it.
To summarize, then, a political system that tries to implement a
right to health care will necessarily involve: forced transfers of
wealth to pay for programs, loss of freedom for health care providers,
higher prices and more restricted access by all consumers, a trend
toward egalitarianism, and the collectivization of health care. These
consequences are not accidental. They follow necessarily from the nature
of the alleged right.
Clinton Plan
The same is true of the Clinton Administration's plan--true on a
much larger scale. This plan will be far more destructive of our
liberties than anything we have experienced so far.
The plan calls for a further extension of health care subsidies: to
those who are currently uninsured, and to those who have health
coverage less extensive than the proposed standard package of benefits.
Where are these subsidies going to come from? The Administration has
rejected the so-called "single-payer system"—that is, overtly socialized
medicine, in which the government pays all the bills—because it knows
that the government cannot pay all the bills. The necessary tax
increases would be politically impossible. So the Clinton plan calls for
a nominally private system in which regulations force some people to
subsidize others.
At the heart of the plan are government-protected monopolies.
At the heart of the plan are the health alliances:
government-protected monopolies in each area which will collect premiums
and negotiate with health care providers to offer acceptable plans.
Everyone who lives in a given area will be forced to obtain health
insurance through their local monopoly health alliance. Health care
providers—private practitioners, HMOs, and others—cannot deal directly
with individuals. They can offer their services only through the health
alliances, subject to the conditions it imposes.
One such condition is guaranteed access: every plan must be willing
to accept any individual who wants it; no one may be excluded for any
reason. Another condition is community rating: the price of the plan
must be the same for everyone. Now think about what effects this will
have on incentives. If I know that when I get sick I will be able to
enroll in any plan I want, at a price that does not reflect my
condition, then I have no reason to obtain health insurance when I am
well. If people are free to choose whether or not to obtain and pay for a
policy, the only people enrolling will be the sick, and costs will go
through the roof. So the system works only if everyone is forced to
participate. That is exactly what the proposal requires, and although
the details of the proposal keep changing, this is one point that cannot
change.
At the national level, the system will be governed by a National
Health Board whose two main functions will be to determine the standard
package of minimum benefits, and to set global budgets. The global
budgets will force the health alliances to impose what amount to price
controls on medical providers. And the standard package of benefits will
be set by interest group lobbying, as every group in the health care
field will try to get its services included in the package. For example,
the current definition of the package includes mental health and
substance abuse counseling. You may feel that you do not need insurance
for these services, but you are going to pay for them.
In short, the plan will require a massive exercise of coercion
against individuals, far beyond anything we have seen so far. Which
brings me back to the fundamental issue.
Moral Foundations
In all the ways I have described, any attempt to implement a
"right" to health care necessarily sacrifices our genuine rights of
liberty. We have to choose between liberty rights and welfare rights.
They are logically incompatible. It is because I believe in the rights
of liberty that I say there is no such thing as a right to health care.
So I want to end by explaining why I think the rights of liberty are
paramount, and by trying to anticipate some of the questions and
objections you may have.
We have to choose between liberty rights and welfare rights.
The rights of liberty are paramount because individuals are ends
in themselves. We are not instruments of society, or possessions of
society. And if we are ends in ourselves, we have the right to be ends
for ourselves: to hold our own lives and happiness as our highest
values, not to be sacrificed for anything else.
I think many people are afraid to assert their rights and interests
as individuals, afraid to assert these rights and interests as moral
absolutes, because they are afraid of being labelled selfish. So it is
vital that we draw certain distinctions. What I am advocating is not
selfishness in the conventional sense: the vain, self-centered, grasping
pursuit of pleasure, riches, prestige, or power. Genuine happiness
results from a life of productive achievement, of stable relationships
with friends and family, of peaceful exchange with others. The pursuit
of our self-interest in this sense requires that we act in accordance
with moral standards of rationality, responsibility, honesty, and
fairness. If we understand the self and its interests in terms of these
values, then I am happy to acknowledge that I am advocating selfishness.
We have to draw the same distinctions when we think about altruism.
For it is, in the end, the moral code of altruism that makes people
think that need is primary, that need gives one a right to the ability
and effort of others. In the conventional sense, altruism means
kindness, generosity, charity, a willingness to help others. These are
certainly virtues, so long as they do not involve the sacrifice of other
values, and so long as they are a matter of personal choice, not a duty
imposed from without. I might note in this regard that physicians have
historically been extremely generous with their time.
More government is not the solution.
In a deeper, philosophical sense, however, altruism is the
principle that one person's need is an absolute claim on others, a claim
that overrides their interests and rights. For example, Dr. Edmund
Pellegrino has asserted, in an article for JAMA, "A medical need
in itself constitutes a moral claim on those equipped to help."[7] This
principle has often been asserted by thinkers who are opposed to
individualism, and it is the basis for the doctrine of welfare rights.
It is the reason why advocates of government involvement in health care
can take for granted that the needs of patients are primary, and that
everyone else can be forced to provide for those needs.
No rational basis for this principle has ever been offered. The
fact is that our needs have to be satisfied by production, not by taking
from others. And production comes from those who take responsibility
for their lives, who apply their minds to the challenges we face in
nature and find new ways of meeting those challenges. Ayn Rand said it best, in her novel The Fountainhead:
"Men have been taught that the highest virtue is not to achieve, but to
give. Yet one cannot give that which has not been created. Creation
comes before distribution—or there will be nothing to distribute. The
need of the creator comes before the need of any possible
beneficiary."[8] The creator's need, in any field, is the freedom to
act, the freedom to dispose of the fruits of his labor as he chooses,
and the freedom to interact with others on a voluntary basis, by trade
and mutual exchange.
That freedom is a vital need, not only for doctors but for
patients. It is only in a context of freedom that one person's need is
not a threat to others. It is only in a context of freedom that genuine
benevolence among people is possible. It is only in a context of freedom
that the medical progress which has brought so many benefits to all of
us can continue.
The problems of our current system were caused by government. More
government is not the solution. But we must oppose the expansion of
government control in principle, by rejecting spurious claims of a
"right" to health care, and insisting on our genuine rights to life,
liberty, property, and the pursuit of happiness.
No comments:
Post a Comment